William Paley's Watchmaker Argument

In William Paley's famous book Natural Theology he puts forth what has become known as the "watchmaker argument."  Many have been quick to toss Paley's argument into the dustbin of refuted arguments, but in his book Reasonable Faith philosopher William Lane Craig points out that many who believe that the argument has failed have most likely never read Paley!

After reading that I started wondering, "I wonder how many have actually read Paley's argument in his own words?"  I invite you to do so now and draw your own conclusions.  It is as follows:

"In crossing a heath, suppose I pitched my foot against a stone, and were asked how the stone came to be there; I might possibly answer, that, for anything I knew to the contrary it had lain there forever: nor would it perhaps be very easy to show the absurdity of this answer.  But suppose I had found a watch upon the ground, and it should be inquired how the watch happened to be in that place; I should hardly think of the answer which I had before given, that, for anything I knew, the watch might have always been there.  Yet why should not this answer serve for the watch as well as for the stone?  Why is it not as admissible in the second case, as in the first?  For this reason, and for no other, viz. that, when we come to inspect the watch, we perceive (what we could not discover in the stone) that its several parts are framed and put together for a purpose, e.g. that they are so formed and adjusted as to produce motion, and that motion so regulated as to point out the hour of the day; that if the different parts had been differently shaped from what they are, of a different size from what they are, or placed after any other manner, or in any other order, than that in which they are placed, either no motion at all would have been carried on in the machine, or none which would have answered the use that is now served by it.  To reckon up a few of the plainest of these parts, and of their offices, all tending to one result: We see a cylindrical box containing a coiled elastic spring, which, by its endeavor to relax itself, turns round the box.  We next observe a flexible chain (artificially wrought for the sake of flexure) communicating the action of the spring from the box to the fusee.  We then find a series of wheels, the teeth of which catch in, and apply to each other, conducting the motion from the fusee to the balance, and from the balance to the pointer; and at the same time, by the size and shape of those wheels, so regulating the motion, as to terminate in causing an index, by an equable and measured progression, to pass over a given space in a given time.  We take notice that the wheels are made of brass in order to keep them from rust; the springs of steel, no other metal being so elastic; that over the face of the watch there is placed a glass, a material employed in no other part of the work; but in the room of which, if there had been any other than a transparent substance, the hour could not be seen without opening the case.  This mechanism being observed (it requires indeed an examination of the instrument, and perhaps some previous knowledge of the subject, to perceive and understand it; but being once, as we have said, observed and understood), the inference, we think, is inevitable; that the watch must have had a maker; that here must have existed, at some time, and at some place or other, an artificer or artificers, who formed it for the purpose which we find it actually to answer; who comprehended its construction, and designed its use." [1]

Paley concludes:

"For every indication of contrivance, every manifestation of design, which existed in the watch, exists in the works of nature, of being greater and more, and that in a degree which exceeds all computation.  I mean, that the contrivances of nature surpass the contrivances of art, in the complexity, subtilty, and curiosity of the mechanism; and still more, if possible, do they go beyond them in number and variety: yet, in a multitude of cases, are not less evidently contrivances, not less evidently accommodated to their end, or suited to their office, than are the most perfect products of human ingenuity." [2]

So, what do you think?  Sound off in the comments below!

If you are interested, you can read Paley's Natural Theology here.

Courage and Godspeed,
Chad

Footnotes:
1. Paley, Natural Theology, 3-4; as quoted by William Lane Craig in Reasonable Faith, 3rd Edition, p. 102-103.
2. Ibid., 13.

Comments